This is one of Austin's most frequently cited papers.
It is of particular interest because it contains in a short space a discussion of its topic together with an explicit account of why the subject is worthwhile and of how it should be studied.
It is a classic account of the motivation and methods of Austin's variant of Philosophical Analysis.
The topic is certain bits of language, particularly "excuses" and other related terms ("plea", "defence", "justification"), and the kinds of situation in which these words are used. |
Because the study of excuses is an important part of a thorough analysis of how we use moral language to talk about behaviour. It provides a "fresh start" to moral philosophy, and "a number of traditional cruces or mistakes in this field can be resolved or removed". Also its a good topic to illustrate methods. |
Justification:
|
|
Good places to look for information about how words are used:
Not clear to what extent these are general methodological suggestions and to what extent they are specific to the particular subject matter under consideration, on the face of it the second two are specific. |
|
Austin's token gesture in this direction would not do for me. I should need some stronger story to convince me how this sort of investigation can contribute to addressing real issues in moral philosophy. In particular, since I doubt there is any limit to how long one can continue this kind of investigation, I would be looking for some clues about how much is enough, and when and how we reap the rewards. Austin shows no signs of caring. He seems so fascinated by this kind of investigation that I doubt he would ever stop to ask whether there is any benefit beyond the discovery of further subtleties in language. |
A surprising emphasis on should, but I see no basis in the method for deciding what we should say as opposed to what we do say, and even less for deciding what we should mean when we do.
Of his justifications, the first two are OK by me, so long as we do not spend so much time cleaning our tools that we have none left for using them. With the third I disagree. Language is not perfect even for time hallowed purposes (particularly for philosophical discussions) and, even if it were it would not suffice for the future. Advances in knowledge are usually closely coupled with refinement, extension, or revolution in language. |
This seems to me to be another token gesture on Austin's part (the first was on motivation).
He mentions very briefly certain criticisms, but does not take them seriously.
Taking up the point about how often people disagree about usage, it is my experience in reading this kind of philosophy, and in reading this particular paper, that I very frequently disagree with points about usage which are presented as self evident, without any other support than the opinion of the author. This especially applies to what Austin says about what we can not do. In common with Wittgenstein, though not quite so conspicuously Austin fails to distinguish ways in which an expression can fail to "make sense". That we fail to make sense of a statement need not mean, and often does not mean, that the statement is in any way pathological. It may simply mean that it asserts something so obvious that we cannot imagine why anyone would bother to state it. In these cases we are not "puzzled" about what the statement means, but rather about why it was said. (of course "means" is a chamelion here, we are unsure about the reasons for making a statement, hence about its significance, and hence about its meaning in a rather more general sense than is generally intended when discussing semantics). Connected with the fallacy that a statement which "makes no sense" must have no meaning, there is the inference from the fact that an expression is rarely or never used to the claim that it is wrong or meaningless to use it. |
Its useful to have something as close as this paper is to an explicit discussion of the methods of linguistic (or connective?) analysis by one of its most respected practitioners. It would be even more useful if one could discern more easily the intended scope of the suggestions. Clearly some of the suggestion are specific to the study of excuses but I'm not clear about which. The law has a particular interest in excuses, does it have any relevance in other applications of analysis? |
|
In summary:
|